Critique of Archaeological Reason
8. Monographs: Wynn

Topological concepts

Giorgio Buccellati – October 2013

Back to top: Topological concepts

Proximity

Placing of blows on rough stone provides a firm clue to intention p. 10f      In order to use topological concepts to analyze stone tools we must ask what spatial notions (there had to be some!) the hominid knapper used while striking one stone onto another. We cannot simply use the geometry of the finished product, because almost every stone tool is topologically equivalent – a three-dimensional solid equivalent to a solid ball (the exceptions are stone rings found in some late assemblages). As a consequence we must step down and look at the arrangement of elements on the tool itself. Certain topological relations can be apprehended from the way in which the knapper positioned trimming flakes during the manufacture of an artifact. In a very real sense, the placing of trimming blows, particularly as they are positioned relative to previous ones, reflects concepts used by the knapper. Three topological notions are especially evident in the trimming patterns of stone tools: proximity, order, and continuity. These represent increasingly complex spatial coordinations.
Significance of contiguity p. 13      The result of contiguous placing of trimming blows is a single prominent edge. One could argue that the flake scars of the previous examples of "proximity only" artifacts (Figures 1 and 2) were also placed contiguously and hence also represent a rudimentary concept of order. This is possible. However, there is nothing about these more primitive artifacts, such as one prominent edge, that required a concept more sophisticated than simple proximity, and, to reiterate a crucial point, we can only argue about minimum competence.
Applying the notion of proximity p. 10f      Perhaps the most rudimentary spatial concept is that of proximity – the perceiving or placing of elements in the same spatial field. It is simply a notion of "nearness" or "byness," and is so basic that virtually every trimmed artifact is equivalent to every other trimmed artifact. Each trimming blow is in some sense "near" the others on the artifact. The only exceptions are unmodified flakes and cores that have had only one trimming blow or, perhaps, two unrelated trimming blows, though it would be difficult if not impossible to prove that the second trimming flake was not placed somehow near the first. From the perspective of this simple spatial notion all trimmed stone artifacts, from polyhedrons to fine bifacial points, are equivalent because multiple trimming flakes have been placed in proximity to one another. Now there is no known artifact assemblage that consists exclusively of unmodified flakes and single-blow cores.
     Competence in proximity is, therefore, a kind of base point from which we can begin to describe the evolution of spatial concepts. As it turns out, there are artifacts whose knapper need only have used a notion of proximity. The following examples are from Bed I at Olduvai.
Specific examples p. 10f       Figure 1 (FLK N). To have made this artifact, the stone knapper need only have struck the cobble repeatedly in the same general vicinity. It was not necessary that he place one blow in some precise relationship to a previous one, only that the blows be more or less near one another. The result was a number of sharp projections and edges that would probably have been useful for several kinds of tasks.
     Figure 2 (DK). At first glance this artifact may appear somewhat more sophisticated than the preceding. There are more trimming flakes, removed by blows from several different angles. Simple bashing would not suffice. Because we can only argue about minimum competence, though, we must conclude that this artifact could have been manufactured by someone who simply placed his trimming blows near other trimming blows.
Wynn proximity       Wynn proximity 2
                     Figure 1                                                            Figure 2

Back to top: Topological concepts

Order – pairing

Applying the notion of pair p. 12      Separation is the notion of distinguishing or segregating the elements in a spatial field so that each can have a specific, rather than general, relation to the others. Order coordinates separation with proximity to create such concepts as the pair, the sequence, and, most complex, the reversible sequence. In a pair, proximity and separation are coordinated but there is no need for a constant direction of movement. The elements in a pair must be distinct yet contiguous, hence the coordination of separation and proximity.
Separation p. 23      If the hominid wanted to make a tool with a single edge, however, proximity alone would not suffice. He would need a concept of separation, in which the edge acts as a kind of boundary or reference separating faces of the tool. He would have to direct his blows with regard to that boundary; this concept is more complex than simple proximity.
Specific examples p. 12f       Figure 3. [...] Four trimming blows have produced a single sharp edge along about one third of the circumference of a cobble. Trimming flakes A and B preceded trimming flakes C and D. In effect, the artifact is the result of two pairs of trimming blows. The order of the blows within each pair is irrelevant, as is the order of the pairs to one another. Again, I am emphasizing how the knapper had to place trimming blows to achieve the result. Bashing in a general vicinity would not have been sufficient. The knapper directed three specific blows (dissociation, separation) to a position adjacent to preceding blows (proximity). Indeed, preceding negative scars appear to have supplied specific striking platforms for subsequent blows. The result is not a random collection of projections and edges but a single working edge. The minimum necessary concept is that of the pair.
     Figure 5. This chopper has at least eleven trimming flakes and, at first glance, appears more sophisticated than the preceding two examples. In addition to simple pairs, the single edge on this chopper required that the concept of separation incorporate several elements. This pattern is intuitively more complicated than that of the simple pair. In mathematical topology, separation is often exemplified by points positioned on opposite sides of a boundary of some sort (inside or outside a circle, for example). On the chopper in Figure 5, the knapper produced a sinuous edge by trimming onto two faces of a cobble. True, the placing of each blow required the idea of a pair in space. But the notion of a single edge also acted as a kind of boundary separating the blows from each face of the tool. What makes this more sophisticated than a simple pair is that the boundary–the edge–had to have been maintained for several trimming blows. This boundary was a spatial reference used by the knapper to orient his blows. The concept of a simple pair was not quite sufficient.
Wynn pair1     Wynn pair2
                     Figure 3                                                            Figure 4

Back to top: Topological concepts

Order – ordered sequence

The notion of ordered sequence p. 14f.      The notion of an ordered sequence requires the coordination of proximity and separation with the addition of a constant direction of movementor orientation. A pair is a pair regardless of the directional orientation of the second element to the first. But if we want to create a series of elements, such as a line of posts, we must employ some concept in addition to separation and nearness. We must place the third element and all subsequent elements in some specific spatial relation to all of the preceding elements. We cannot simply place the third post near the second; we must also consider the position of the first. This is most easily done by maintaining a constant direction of movement. This coordination is more complex than that of the pair because several distinct elements (separation) must be related through some concept of arrangement, even one as simple as "move to the left".
Specific examples p. 14-17
     Figure 6a (FLK N). In the view shown here, the lower edge of the artifact consists of a series of six unifacial flake scars. On close examination one can see that the knapper did not strike off the trimming flakes one after another in exact sequence (at least one is out of place; see arrow). Consequently, any comparison to a strict sequence such as ABCDEF would be spurious. Nevertheless, the end result is the same–one flake scar following another. The violation of a strict order should not be disturbing. It is unlikely that these early hominids played logical games with themselves, at least using stone tools. Wynn ordered sequence
     The coordination of proximity and order in this artifact is certainly more complex than that of a pair. Each flake is placed in relation not just to another one but to all of the other flake scars. The knapper achieved this result by restricting successive trimming blows to a single direction. This constant direction of movement is the third notion in a concept of order.
     Figure 6b. This example differs from earlier ones in that it is a flake tool; that is, the blank itself was a flake rather than a cobble or a chunk of stone. This implies two major manufacturing steps–the removal of the flake from a core and the subsequent trimming of the flake. While this increase in number of steps reflects a greater complexity of sorts, it is of no direct relevance to a discussion of spatial concepts, especially since we have no way of knowing whether the whole sequence was conceived at the outset or whether the knapper simply selected a previously struck flake as most appropriate for the task at hand. The spatial concepts necessary for trimming this flake are identical to those used on the cobble in the preceding example.
     Figure 6c. This small scraper was also made on a flake. The trimming flakes are related to one another in the same manner as those of the two preceding examples. What is important here is the small size of the trimming flakes; the knapper needed a fairly fine motor control to make this artifact. The "primitiveness" of Oldowan tools cannot, therefore, be explained in terms of poor motor coordination on the part of the hominids. In makingthese three artifacts, Oldowan hominids employed a spatial concept more sophisticated than that of a simple pair. Put abstractly, we can argue for a concept of linear order. Each element, in this case trimming flakes, was placed in relation to several other elements, the result being a sequence. Though their order was not as elegant as a purely mathematical series such as ABCDEF, it is still clear that these hominids were capable of arranging a sequence of elements.

Back to top: Topological concepts

Order – reversed sequence

The notion of reversed sequence (symmetry) p. 17      [...] there are some kinds of artifacts that required a reversal, though the spatial elements were more abstract than simple trimming flakes. I am referring, of course, to bifaces, whose bilateral symmetry requires the reversal of order around a midline. ABC/CBA is a symmetry.

Back to top: Topological concepts

Continuity

Breaking down and putting back together p. 18      [ ] the relationship of parts to a whole. A line is, topologically, an infinite series of indiscernably small points. In order to conceive of a line in this fashion, it is necessary to be able to subdivide the line infinitely and then recreate it in thought from the resulting elements. Stated in another way, one must analyze a whole (the line) into its constituent elements (the points) and resynthesize these elements into the whole. It is a breaking down and putting back together which, in terms of simpler topological relations, requires the coordination of proximity, separation, and order. Such whole-part relations are among the most sophisticated of topological notions and, if we can get at them, should be quite important in characterizing the spatial competence of early hominids.

[A relatively late development: the book discusses at this point the question of possible transitional items.]
intention p. 18       For objects such as the choppers and scrapers of previous examples it is impossible to make judgments about minimal trimming because we have little idea of the knapper's intention concerning overall shape, if in fact he had one. But for artifacts with symmetry or regularity of any arbitrary kind we can make such judgments, keeping in mind that they are, in fact, judgments
Example p. 19
     The symmetry of this particular biface resulted from four short sections of trimming (A, B, C, and D) that are, for the most part, unconnected with each other. In order to have done this the knapper needed some notion of the shape broken down into potential constituent elements, in this case trimming flakes, and of their combination into the finished whole–in other words, a fairly sophisticated idea of the spatial relation of parts to the whole. Wynn continuity
Figure 7
Only by reducing the shape to potential trimming flakes could he have determined which were necessary and which were not. Again, we need not envision the hominid in agonizing contemplation, but even quick, on-the-spot planning required a notion of whole and part.