Critique of Archaeological Reason
8. Monographs: Wynn
Methodology
Giorgio Buccellati, October 2013
Nature and limits
Developmental sequence
Nature of progress
Structure
Bracing
Typology and taxonomy
About archaeology
Nature and limits
Qualitative analysis |
p. 3f. |
Such a qualitative technique may appear sacrilegious in this age of
indices
and computer analysis, but there is a sound reason for it: quantification would accomplish nothing. |
Concentrating on exceptional pieces |
p. 32 |
[...] such artifacts are by no means the most common.
Almost all biface assemblages, even very late ones, have crude bifaces
with irregular cross sections. In many assemblages these predominate. Nevertheless, in a study such as this one, which is concerned
with the evolution of a competence, it is fair, I think, to focus on the
exceptional pieces. |
Back to top: Monographs/Wynn
Developmental sequences
Gaps in sequence |
p. 33 |
As was the case with the projective straight line, the developmental
sequence of the notion of regular cross section is far from complete. |
No intermediate stage for straight edge |
p. 38f |
What is not clear is the development of these projective abilities. No
argument can be made for projective relations during the Oldowan.
No straight edges exist, and there are no intentionally regular cross
sections. The West Natron artifacts are more equivocal. Some are extensively trimmed, some have vaguely straight sides, and some of the
bifaces have somewhat regular cross sections. [...] In other words the
"intermediate" position of West Natron artifacts in regard to topological relations is not corroborated by their position in regard to projective relations. These appear to have been a relatively late addition
to the hominid repertoire. |
Late date for euclidean concepts |
p. 39f |
The idea of space as a general
framework of positions is one that develops during ontogeny, and, as
I hope to show in this section, it appeared in the behavior of early
humans by 300,000 years ago. [...] there is early evidence
for a concept of measurement but not for one of parallel axes, a fact
that has interesting implications for the evolution of euclidean space. |
Seriation problems |
p. 54f |
If we limit our consideration of symmetry to euclidean concepts of
congruency, perpendicular and bisected lines, and so on, then the
developmental sequence presented by stone tools consists of only two
stagesearly stone tools for which an argument for symmetry cannot
be made, and later artifacts, like those from Isimila, for which it must
be made. This is not much of a sequence, and, in fact, it tells us nothing about the antecedents of euclidean notions, which is just what we
would like to know. |
Overview |
p. 58 |
It seems that the development of a general frame of spatial
reference did not include an "affine" stage of competence in parallels,
but did include the relatively early appearance of notions of interval,
shape, and mirroring.
|
Ape-like stage for Olduwan |
p. 63 |
Oldowan hominids attended to the nature of the edgeprobably
tied to a specific task at handand paid no attention to the overall
shape of their tools. These edges required, as we have seen, only rudimentary spatial concepts. Indeed, in many respects these tools resemble tools made by modern chimpanzees. Both have simple modifications tied to an immediate task, and both are spatially simple. [...] in terms of spatial concepts, Oldowan
tools look very ape-like.
|
Back to top: Monographs/Wynn
Nature of progress in the Paleolithic
No cumulation |
p. 62f. |
It is my contention
that spatial concepts did not accrue in additive fashion, like the reading of a geometry text, but were acquired in
constellations of
concepts tied, ultimately, to single overriding idea or conceptual
breakthroughs. These breakthroughs were unlikely to have resulted from conscious theorizing on the part of individual hominids. They
were, rather, developments within the repertoire of day-to-day spatial
strategies that yielded more pleasing or desirable results. Nevertheless, these developments opened up many new possibilities for artifact form. |
Back to top: Monographs/Wynn
Structure
There is no specific discussion of structure in the book, but the central notion is implied by the following remarks.
No analysis of structure per se |
p. 3 |
The analyses in this book concern, therefore, the
patterns of trimming found on tools. Occasionally they also consider
the overall shape of the artifact, but only in cases where it is clearly
the result of extensive trimming. |
Sequential complexity [as a clue to structure] |
p. 12 |
Separation is the notion of distinguishing or segregating the elements in a spatial field so that each can have a specific,
rather than general, relation to the others. Order coordinates separation with proximity to create such concepts as the pair, the sequence,
and, most complex, the reversible sequence. |
Non random sequence of blows |
p. 13 |
The knapper directed three specific blows (dissociation, separation) to a position adjacent to preceding blows (proximity). Indeed,
preceding negative scars appear to have supplied specific striking
platforms for subsequent blows. The result is not a random collection
of projections and edges but a single working edge. The minimum
necessary concept is that of the pair. |
Relation of single constituents to the whole |
p. 15 |
Each flake is placed in relation not just to
another one but to all of the other flake scars. The knapper achieved
this result by restricting successive trimming blows to a single direction. This constant direction of movement is the third notion in a
concept of order. |
p. 18 |
The final topological notion of use in analyzing stone tools is that
of continuitythe relationship of parts to a whole. A line is, topoIogically, an infinite series of indiscernably small points. In order to
conceive of a line in this fashion, it is necessary to be able to subdivide
the line infinitely and then recreate it in thought from the resulting
elements. Stated in another way, one must analyze a whole (the line)
into its constituent elements (the points) and resynthesize these elements into the whole. |
p. 19 |
[...] we need not envision the hominid in agonizing contemplation, but even quick, on-the-spot planning
required a notion of whole and part. |
Linear order |
p. 17 |
Put abstractly, we can argue for a concept of linear order. Each element, in
this case trimming flakes, was placed in relation to several other elements, the result being a sequence. |
Potential elements of the whole |
p. 19 |
In order to have done this the knapper
needed some notion of the shape broken down into potential constituent elements, in this case trimming flakes, and of their combination
into the finished wholein other words, a fairly sophisticated idea of
the spatial relation of parts to the whole. |
Whole to parts, 300,000 years ago |
p. 62 |
the notion of
whole-part relations, the understanding of the spatial relationship of
a whole to its constituent parts. The minimally trimmed bifaces required an idea of final shape (which could include the euclidean
notions discussed above) and also an awareness of the minimum
modifications required to achieve that shape. The knapper had to
understand how each possible modification would affect the result, and
choose accordingly. Trial-and-error knapping, even with constant
checking, would be insufficient.
|
Back to top: Monographs/Wynn
Bracing
The term and the notion as such are missing in the book, but the ability to distinguish and to unite non contiguous elements (para-perception) is implied by the following.
Analysis and synthesis |
p. 18 |
In order to
conceive of a line in this fashion, it is necessary to be able to subdivide
the line infinitely and then recreate it in thought from the resulting
elements. Stated in another way, one must analyze a whole (the line)
into its constituent elements (the points) and resynthesize these elements into the whole. It is a breaking down and putting back together
which, in terms of simpler topological relations, requires the coordination of proximity, separation, and order. Such whole-part relations
are among the most sophisticated of topological notions and, if we
can get at them, should be quite important in characterizing the spatial competence of early hominids. It is obviously impossible to see an
infinitely small point or to inquire about understandings of lines.
However, it is possible to examine the results of the process of analysis
and synthesis, the ability to break a whole into constituent elements
and put it back together again. |
Coordinating viewpoints |
p. 28 |
As is true of the topological concept of analysis and synthesis,
there is good evidence for consideration of perspective in later Acheulean bifaces. This competence included not only the ability to operate from one stable viewpoint but the ability to coordinate viewpoints. This conclusion is corroborated by the evidence from cross
sections. |
Back to top: Monographs/Wynn
Typology and taxonomy
No standard modern typology |
p. 4 |
The analysis does not use any standard archaeological typology. I
do use some archaeological terms such as "scraper" and "handaxe"
but only as convenient terms of reference. The implied function in
such terms is irrelevant. Indeed, the purpose for which the hominid
made the tools is not at issue. [...] A hominid
could have made two tools with very different tasks in mind, but if he
used the same spatial notions to conceive both of them, then, from
the point of view of this analysis, the tools are equivalent. There is a
typology of sorts inherent in the analysis. It consists solely of spatial
relationships identified on the toolsproximity and symmetry, for
example. |
No isolated assemblages of items that are based only on proximity |
p. 11 |
...
there is no known artifact assemblage that consists exclusively of unmodified flakes and single-blow cores. |
p. 12 |
... there is no known assemblage that consists entirely of artifacts
of such simplicity. However, it is at least conceivable that an assemblage of such artifacts did in fact constitute the earliest recognizable
(though as yet unrecognized) set of stone tools. |
Back to top: Monographs/Wynn
About archaeology
Archaeology is "optimistic" |
p. vii |
Archaeology is by nature an
optimistic discipline that strives to build an understanding of the past
out of small and fragmented pieces. |
Not fossilized theories |
p. 57 |
The artifacts themselves
are not fossilized theories but
they do supply clues to the
antecedents
of such a general frame of reference |
Back to top: Monographs/Wynn
|